Up until recently, I had thought that natural law theory was compatible with moral arguments formulated as follows:
- If God does not exist, then objective moral values and duties do not exist.
- Objective moral values and duties do exist.
- Therefore, God exists.
Moral arguments of this kind have been made popular by defenders such as CS Lewis and William Lane Craig, and this specific formulation comes from the latter. In a post from a few years ago I explained my position on the compatibility of this with natural law theory as follows:
I think technically we can still use [the argument] as [formulated above], but we must recognise that it is partly dependent upon something like the fifth way for its soundness. At the end of the day I think much moral debate can be had without reference to God, since it is based on what is knowable about our nature. But ultimately I think any viable ethics depends on God, including natural law. (section 4.1)
This is admittedly not giving much credit to the argument, but I have since realized that even this weak support for the moral argument is misplaced. It seems to me that once we clarify the above formulation, the first premise will be seen to be incompatible with natural law theory, or at least some increasingly popular versions of it.
To start on the more technical side of things, the first premise should be understood as a non-trivially true counterfactual with an impossible antecedent (see here for details):
1′. If God did not exist, then objective moral values and duties would not exist.
So far there is still no obvious incompatibility with natural law theory, but we can go further. Presumably, if we are running this argument, then we think that there is something special about moral values and duties that calls out for a theistic explanation. That is, we are not interested in the general fact that anything whatsoever exists, but particularly the fact that moral values and duties exist. If this were not the case, then wouldn’t really be running a moral argument at all, but would instead be running a cosmological argument.
The point of the first premise, then, is that we finite agents are not sufficient to account for objective moral standards, and so the presence of such standards would imply the existence of God. This suggests that another way of stating the first premise is as follows:
1*. If we were to exist without God, then objective moral values and duties would not exist.
(Those of us who are convinced that God is required to account for any existence should also read this as a non-trivially true counterfactual with an impossible antecedent.)
Apart from the reasoning that got us here, further confirmation that (1*) captures the intent of (1) comes from how the premise is often defended. Consider, for instance, the following quote from Craig:
If there is no God, then any ground for regarding the herd morality evolved by homo sapiens as objectively true seems to have been removed. After all, what is so special about human beings? They are just accidental by-products of nature which have evolved relatively recently on an infinitesimal speck of dust lost somewhere in a hostile and mindless universe and which are doomed to perish individually and collectively in a relatively short time. Some action, say, incest, may not be biologically or socially advantageous and so in the course of human evolution has become taboo; but there is on the atheistic view nothing really wrong about committing incest. If, as Kurtz states, “The moral principles that govern our behavior are rooted in habit and custom, feeling and fashion,” then the non-conformist who chooses to flout the herd morality is doing nothing more serious than acting unfashionably. (William Lane Craig, The Indispensability of Theological Meta-Ethical Foundations for Morality)
Notice that this line of argument envisions a world where we exist without God, and puzzles over where moral values and duties are supposed to come from in such a world.
Now, while natural law theory may not pose any obvious problem for (1) or (1′), once we recognize that these amount to (1*) the problem becomes clear. The whole burden of a natural law theory is to ground moral truths in the natures of things, and having the nature that we do is part of what it means for us to exist. In the world described by (1*), then, the fact that we still exist with natures means that we still have objective moral duties and values even though God is not in the picture — at least from the perspective of natural law.
Of course, the exact details of this will differ depending on the version of natural law theory we consider. On Platonism these natures will be unchanging Forms in some third realm, on Aristotelianism they are intrinsic teleologies in things, and the new natural lawyers focus more on the nature of practical reason than on the natures of things. And each of these has variants within it. Some versions of Platonism equate the Forms with divine ideas, so that taking God out of the picture will take out natures with him. But other versions have God completely separate, meaning that natures stay even after God is removed.
Thomistic natural law theory is of the Aristotelian variety and is the version I find most compelling. On the one hand, it agrees with Aristotle that morality is fundamentally grounded in the intrinsic teleology built into us by virtue of the natures we have. On the other hand, contrary to Aristotle, it says that this intrinsic teleology still depends on God. Mind you, not in a way that makes it distinct from our nature, as if our teleology could in any way be separated from what we are. Rather, it is by creating and sustaining us as the kinds of creatures we are that God upholds the intrinsic teleology that fundamentally grounds morality. Of course, the details of this are quite complicated, but the point is that on the Thomistic view our intrinsic teleology is not mutually exclusive with God being the cause of our nature.
This brings us back to (1*). This premise asks us to consider the world where per impossible God does not exist and yet we still do. Because in such a world we still exist, we also still have natures and the intrinsic teleology which fundamentally grounds morality. This remains true even if our natures arose through blind evolutionary processes since what’s important is the nature we have, not how we got it. So, in this world where we exist without God there is still the foundational morality that arises from the natural law: it is still wrong for us to lie, to murder, to steal, etc.; we still have categorical obligations, are held accountable, and have a basis for moral authorities (see section 2.4 here); we still have objective virtues and vices; actions are still objectively good and bad. Of course, there will be no duties arising from divine commands, but on natural law theories, these are in addition to the natural law, not instead of it.
So, then, for those of us who accept the Thomistic account of natural law, the moral argument we’re considering should be rejected as unsound. And I suspect the same would be true for some other versions of natural law theory, whether they be Platonic, Aristotelian, or from the new natural lawyers. It is certainly true for Aristotle’s own version, which doesn’t even construe God as the cause of our intrinsic teleology. On the other hand, there is also a lesson for those defenders of the argument who don’t accept any of these natural law accounts: a full defense of the first premise requires a thorough critique of these different natural law theories, which is no simple task. Certainly not as simple as the quote above appears. After all, natural law theories have a long pedigree in the history of Western thought.
While this objection doesn’t affect all moral arguments, it is noteworthy because the version it does affect is quite common. The argument might still have apologetic value insofar as it could convince someone who already rejects natural law, but such a rhetorical strategy makes me somewhat uneasy.
I have a hard time thinking about impossible worlds ( i have a hard time thinking about them clearly) but i think that a theistic Aristotelian could employ what might be called the Aratus principle “in him we live and move and have our being” to demonstrate the compatibility of natural law theory with the moral argument. I don’t have a lot of time to work through it clearly either but i think the solution would be found by someone considering these two principles:
1** (The Aratus principle – Acts 17:28) In an impossible world in which the Human existed but there was no God the human would have no essence (Aristotelian principle of action/being).
1*** (Natural Law theory): In an impossible world in which the human existed but her essence didn’t the human would lack moral law.
Joshua, I share your discomfort with impossible worlds. I have some thoughts on your comment, but before that: surely the principle you draw from Acts 17:28 should be called the Epimenides principle? If I’m not mistaken, Aratus is the source of the other quote: “For we are indeed his offspring.”
Pedantics aside, I have three points regarding your (1**) and (1***).
First, at least for some of the metaphysical views of these natural law accounts, to speak of “a human without an essence” is as coherent as speaking of “a square without sides”. This is true for Aristotelian and Thomistic metaphysics, and I suspect it’s true of at least some Platonic metaphysics as well, since on these an individual exists by virtue of imitating a particular Form. Now, while I agree that existing without God’s concurrence is impossible, it doesn’t seem to rise to the level of incoherence. Perhaps the problem is that essence is an intrinsic principle of my existence, while an efficient cause is extrinsic. I’m not sure.
Second, the moral argument here is trying to envision a world as similar to our world as possible minus God, which is why we can still intelligibly speak of evolutionary processes and humans in the impossible world being envisioned. Given this, it seems that we should retain our essences and natures in this impossible world, unless the particular metaphysics makes this impossible. I mentioned one such example in the post itself, namely the version of Platonism where the Forms are divine ideas — of course it makes no sense to speak of divine ideas separate to a divine thinker. But the other views can happily talk about essences and natures apart from God and so they should be kept.
Third, it seems to me that once we go through (1**) we’re back in the situation I mention where we’re not actually running a moral argument anymore. Once you have (1**), you’re introducing moral premises as a distraction from an otherwise more straightforward cosmological argument:
(1**) If we existed without God, then we would not have essences.
(2**) We have essences.
(3) Therefore, God exists.
Surely it is more evident that we have essences (of the type you’d need to explicate in the defense of (1**)) than that moral duties and values exist.
[…] law theory and morality. Can the two be combined? Specifically, I will be responding to Roland’s excellent post on the topic which claims they are incompatible. Please go check out his blog first and then head on back here. […]
From what I can glean from these thoughts and others, natural law is the idea that human nature is sufficient to interpret morality, and that the definition of morality should include individual interpretation, as well as the interpretation of the herd, but regards the role of absolute authority as secondary to the apparent needs of humanity.
Under this philosophy, it would seem to me that the Catholic view of the ‘end justifying the means’ becomes valid to those that lean on the philosophy. In other words, for example, it would be acceptable to lie and deceive if it appears that it is serving the greater good
Also there are elements that fit into Marxism since serving the greater good becomes the moral responsibility, and that is decided by the representative of the herd and their ideals but appeals to the morality of the individual who rejects religious definitions of right conduct.
Therefore natural law also applies to the social justice movement, which is apparently derived from Marxism, as the needs of the minorities are considered equally valid with the needs of the majority, but without necessarily referring to Biblical views of absolute authority and unchanging law.
But, to recapitulate, when combined with religious views, natural law philosophy regards the Moral Law of scripture as the ideal, but that the desire of man alone is sufficient to achieve morality and that the moral code is merely a guide to a destination.